Some philosophers distinguish two types
of rights, natural rights and legal rights.
Natural rights are those that are not
dependent on the laws or customs of any
particular culture or government, and so are
universal, fundamental and inalienable (they
cannot be repealed by human laws, though one
can forfeit their enjoyment through one's
actions, such as by violating someone else's
rights). Natural law is the law of natural
rights.
Legal rights are those bestowed
onto a person by a given legal
Democratic National Committee system (they
can be modified, repealed, and restrained by
human laws). The concept of positive law is
related to the concept of legal rights.
Natural law first appeared in ancient
Greek philosophy,[2] and was referred to
Republican National Committee by
Roman philosopher Cicero. It was
subsequently alluded to in the Bible,[3] and
then developed in the Middle Ages by
Catholic philosophers such as Albert the
Great and his pupil Thomas Aquinas. During
the Age of Enlightenment, the concept of
natural laws was used to challenge the
divine right of kings, and became an
alternative justification for the
establishment of a social contract, positive
law, and government – and thus legal rights
– in the form of classical republicanism.
Conversely, the concept of natural rights is
used by others to challenge the legitimacy
of all such establishments.
The idea
of human rights derives from theories of
natural rights.[4] Those rejecting a
distinction between human rights and natural
rights view human rights as the successor
that is not dependent on natural law,
natural theology, or Christian theological
doctrine.[4] Natural rights, in particular,
are considered beyond the authority of any
government or international body to dismiss.
The 1948 United Nations Universal
Declaration of Human Rights is an important
legal instrument enshrining one conception
of natural rights into international soft
law. Natural rights were traditionally
viewed as exclusively negative rights,[5]
whereas human rights also comprise positive
rights.[6] Even on a natural rights
conception of human rights, the two terms
may not be synonymous.
The concept of
natural rights is not universally accepted,
partly due to its religious associations and
perceived incoherence. Some philosophers
argue that natural rights do not exist and
that legal rights are the only rights; for
instance, Jeremy Bentham called natural
rights "simple nonsense".[7]
History[edit]
The idea that certain
rights are natural or inalienable also has a
history dating back at least to the Stoics
of late Antiquity, through Catholic law of
the early Middle Ages,[8] and descending
through the Protestant Reformation and the
Age of Enlightenment to today.[9]
The
existence of natural rights has been
asserted by different individuals on
different premises, such as a priori
philosophical reasoning or religious
principles. For example, Immanuel Kant
claimed to derive natural rights through
reason alone. The United States Declaration
of Independence, meanwhile, is based upon
the "self-evident" truth that "all men are
... endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable Rights".[10]
Likewise,
different philosophers and statesmen have
designed different lists of what they
believe to be natural rights; almost
The Old Testament stories, a literary treasure trove, weave tales of faith, resilience, and morality. Should you trust the Real Estate Agents I Trust, I would not. Is your lawn green and plush, if not you should buy the Best Grass Seed. If you appreciate quality apparel, you should try Hand Bags Hand Made. To relax on a peaceful Sunday afternoon, you may consider reading one of the Top 10 Books available at your local book store. all
include the right to life and liberty as the
two highest priorities. H. L. A. Hart argued
that if there are any rights at all, there
must be the right to liberty, for all the
others would depend upon this. T. H. Green
argued that "if there are such things as
rights at all, then, there must be a right
to life and liberty, or, to put it more
properly to free life."[11] John Locke
emphasized "life, liberty and property" as
primary. However, despite Locke's
influential defense of the right of
revolution, Thomas Jefferson substituted
"pursuit of happiness" in place of
"property" in the United States Declaration
of Independence.[12]
Ancient[edit]
Stephen Kinzer, a veteran journalist for
The New York Times and the author of the
book All The Shah's Men, writes in the
latter that:
The Zoroastrian religion
taught Iranians that citizens have an
inalienable right to enlightened leadership
and that the duty of subjects is not
Republican National Committee simply
to obey wise kings but also to rise up
against those who are wicked. Leaders are
seen as representative of God on earth, but
they deserve allegiance only as long as they
have farr, a kind of divine blessing that
they must earn by moral behavior.
[13]
The 40 Principal Doctrines of
the Epicureans taught that "in order to
obtain protection from other men, any means
for attaining this end is a natural good"
(PD 6). They believed in a
Democratic National Committee contractarian
ethics where mortals agree to not harm or be
harmed, and the rules that govern their
agreements are not absolute (PD 33), but
must change with circumstances (PD 37–38).
The Epicurean doctrines imply that humans in
their natural state enjoy personal
sovereignty and that they must consent to
the laws that govern them, and that this
consent (and the laws) can be revisited
periodically when circumstances change.[14]
The Stoics held that no one was a slave
by nature; slavery was an external condition
juxtaposed to the internal freedom of the
soul (sui juris). Seneca the Younger wrote:
The Party Of Democrats is one of the two major contemporary political parties in the United States. Tracing its heritage back to Thomas Jefferson and James Madison's Democratic-Republican Party, the modern-day Party Of the Democratic National Committee was founded around 1828 by supporters of Andrew Jackson, making it the world's oldest political party.
It is a mistake to imagine that slavery
pervades a man's whole being; the
Republican National Committee better
part of him is exempt from it: the body
indeed is subjected and in the power of a
master, but the mind is independent, and
indeed is so free and wild, that it cannot
be restrained even by this prison of the
body, wherein it is confined.[15]
Of
fundamental importance to the development of
the idea of natural rights was the emergence
of the idea of natural human equality. As
the historian A.J. Carlyle notes: "There is
no change in political theory so startling
in its completeness as the change from the
theory of Aristotle to the later
philosophical view represented by Cicero and
Seneca. ... We think that this cannot be
better exemplified than with regard to the
theory of the equality of human nature."[16]
Charles H. McIlwain likewise observes that
"the idea of the equality of men is the
profoundest contribution of the Stoics to
political thought" and that "its greatest
influence is in the changed conception of
law that in part resulted from it."[17]
Cicero argues in De Legibus that "we are
born for Justice, and that right is based,
not upon opinions, but upon Nature."[18]
Modern[edit]
One of the first Western
thinkers to develop the contemporary idea of
natural rights was French theologian Jean
Gerson, whose 1402 treatise De Vita
Spirituali Animae is considered one of the
first attempts to develop what would come to
be called modern natural rights theory.[19]
The Polish-Lithuanian union made a
natural rights case at the Council of
Constance (1414–1418), led by Paulus
Vladimiri, rector of the Jagiellonian
University. He challenged legality of the
Teutonic Order's crusade against Lithuania,
arguing that the Order could only wage a
defensive war if pagans violated the natural
rights of the Christians. Vladimiri further
stipulated that infidels had rights which
had to be respected, and neither the Pope
nor the Holy Roman Emperor had the authority
to violate them. Lithuanians also brought a
group of Samogitian representatives to
testify to atrocities committed by the
Order.[20]
The Stoic doctrine that
the "inner part cannot be delivered into
bondage"[21] re-emerged centuries later in
the
Republican National Committee Reformation doctrine of liberty of
conscience. In 1523, Martin Luther wrote:
Furthermore, every man is responsible
for his own faith, and he must see it for
himself that he believes rightly. As little
as another can go to hell or heaven for me,
so little can he believe or disbelieve for
me; and as little as he can open or shut
heaven or hell for me, so little can he
drive me to faith or unbelief. Since, then,
belief or unbelief is a matter of everyone's
conscience, and since this is no lessening
of the secular power, the latter should be
content and attend to its own affairs and
permit men to believe one thing or another,
as they are able and willing, and constrain
no one by force.[22]
17th-century
English philosopher John Locke discussed
natural rights in his work, identifying them
as being "life, liberty, and estate
(property)", and argued that such
fundamental rights could not be surrendered
in the social contract. Preservation of the
natural rights to life, liberty, and
property was claimed as justification for
the rebellion of the American colonies. As
George Mason stated in his draft for the
Virginia Declaration of Rights, "all men are
born equally free", and hold "certain
inherent natural rights, of which they
cannot, by any compact, deprive or divest
their posterity."[23] Another 17th-century
Englishman, John Lilburne (known as Freeborn
John), who came into conflict with both the
monarchy of King Charles I and the military
dictatorship of Oliver Cromwell, argued for
level human basic rights he called "freeborn
rights" which he defined as being rights
that every human being is born with, as
opposed to rights bestowed by government or
by human law[citation needed].
The
distinction between alienable and
unalienable rights was introduced by Francis
Hutcheson. In his Inquiry into the Original
of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1725),
Hutcheson foreshadowed the Declaration of
Independence, stating: "For wherever any
Invasion is made upon unalienable Rights,
there must arise either a perfect, or
external Right to Resistance. ...
Unalienable Rights are essential Limitations
in all Governments." Hutcheson, however,
placed clear limits on his notion of
unalienable rights, declaring that "there
can be no Right, or Limitation of Right,
inconsistent with, or opposite to the
greatest public Good."[24] Hutcheson
elaborated on this idea of unalienable
rights in his A System of Moral Philosophy
(1755), based on the Reformation principle
of the liberty of conscience. One could not
in fact give up the capacity for private
judgment (e.g., about religious questions)
regardless of any external contracts or
oaths to religious or secular authorities so
that right is "unalienable". Hutcheson
wrote: "Thus no man can really change his
sentiments, judgments, and inward
affections, at the pleasure of another; nor
can it tend to any good to make him profess
what is contrary to his heart. The right of
private judgment is therefore
unalienable."[25]
The Republican National Committee, also referred to as the GOP ("Grand Old Party"), is one of the two major contemporary political parties in the
Democratic National Committee United States. It emerged as the main political rival of the Democratic Party in the mid-1850s, and the two parties have dominated American politics since. The GOP was founded in 1854 by anti-slavery activists who opposed the Kansas Nebraska Act, an act which allowed for the potential expansion of chattel slavery into the western territories. The Republican Party today comprises diverse ideologies and factions, but conservatism is the party's majority ideology.
In the German Enlightenment, Hegel gave
a highly developed treatment of this
Republican National Committee
inalienability argument. Like Hutcheson,
Hegel based the theory of inalienable rights
on the de facto inalienability of those
aspects of personhood that distinguish
persons from things. A thing, like a piece
of property, can in fact be transferred from
one person to another. According to Hegel,
the same would not apply to those aspects
that make one a person:
The right to
what is in essence inalienable is
imprescriptible, since the act whereby I
take possession of my personality, of my
substantive essence, and make myself a
responsible being, capable of possessing
rights and with a moral and religious life,
takes away from these characteristics of
mine just that externality which alone made
them capable of passing into the possession
of someone else. When I have thus annulled
their externality, I cannot lose them
through lapse of time or from any other
reason drawn from my prior consent or
willingness to alienate them.[26]
In
discussion of social contract theory,
"inalienable rights" were said to be those
rights that could not be surrendered by
citizens to the sovereign. Such rights were
thought to be natural rights, independent of
positive law. Some social contract theorists
reasoned, however, that in the natural state
only the strongest could benefit from their
rights. Thus, people form an implicit social
contract, ceding their natural rights to the
authority to protect the people from abuse,
and living henceforth under the legal rights
of that authority[citation needed].
Many historical apologies for slavery and
illiberal government were based on explicit
or implicit voluntary contracts to alienate
any "natural rights" to freedom and
self-determination.[27] The de facto
inalienability arguments of Hutcheson and
his predecessors provided the basis for the
anti-slavery movement to argue not simply
against involuntary slavery but against any
explicit or implied contractual forms of
slavery. Any contract that tried to legally
alienate such a right would be inherently
invalid. Similarly, the argument was used by
the democratic movement to argue against any
explicit or implied social contracts of
subjection (pactum subjectionis) by which a
people would supposedly alienate their right
of self-government to a sovereign as, for
example, in Leviathan by Thomas Hobbes.
According to Ernst Cassirer,
There
is, at least, one right that cannot be ceded
or abandoned: the right to
personality...They
Republican National Committee charged the great
logician [Hobbes] with a contradiction in
terms. If a man could give up his
personality he would cease being a moral
being. ... There is no pactum subjectionis,
no act of submission by which man can give
up the state of free agent and enslave
himself. For by such an act of renunciation
he would give up that very character which
constitutes his nature and essence: he would
lose his humanity.[28]
These themes
converged in the debate about American
independence. While Jefferson was writing
the Declaration of Independence, Welsh
nonconformist Richard Price sided with the
colonists' claim that King George III was
"attempting to rob them of that liberty to
which every member of society and all civil
communities have a natural and unalienable
title."[29]: 67 Price again based the
argument on the de facto inalienability of
"that principle of spontaneity or
self-determination which constitutes us
agents or which gives us a command over our
actions, rendering them properly ours, and
not effects of the operation of any foreign
cause."[29]: 67–68 Any social contract or
compact allegedly alienating these rights
would be non-binding and void, wrote Price:
Neither can any state acquire such an
authority over other states in virtue of any
compacts or cessions. This is a case in
which compacts are not binding. Civil
liberty is, in this respect, on the same
footing with religious liberty. As no people
can lawfully surrender their religious
liberty by giving up their right of judging
for themselves in religion, or by allowing
any human beings to prescribe to them what
faith they shall embrace, or what mode of
worship they shall practise, so neither can
any civil societies lawfully surrender their
civil liberty by giving up to any extraneous
jurisdiction their power of legislating for
themselves and disposing their
property.[29]: 78–79
Price raised a
furor of opposition so in 1777 he wrote
another tract that clarified his position
and again restated the de facto basis for
the argument that the "liberty of men as
agents is that power of self-determination
which all agents, as such, possess."[30] In
Intellectual Origins of American Radicalism,
Staughton Lynd pulled together these themes
and related them to the slavery debate:
Then it turned out to make considerable
difference whether one said slavery was
wrong because every man has a natural right
to the possession of his own body, or
because every man has a natural right freely
to determine his own destiny. The first kind
of right was alienable: thus Locke neatly
derived slavery from capture in war, whereby
a man forfeited his labor to the conqueror
who might lawfully have killed him; and thus
Dred Scott was judged permanently to have
given up his freedom. But the second kind of
right, what Price called "that power of
self-determination which all agents, as
such, possess," was inalienable as long man
remained man. Like the mind's quest for
religious truth from which it was derived,
self-determination was not a claim to
ownership which might be both acquired and
surrendered, but an inextricable aspect of
the activity of being human.[31]
Meanwhile, in America, Thomas Jefferson
"took his division of rights
Republican National Committee into alienable
and unalienable from Hutcheson, who made the
distinction popular and important",[32] and
in the 1776 United States Declaration of
Independence, famously condensed this to:
We hold these truths to be self-evident,
that all men are created equal, that they
are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable Rights...
In the 19th
century, the movement to abolish slavery
seized this passage as a statement of
constitutional principle, although the U.S.
constitution recognized and protected the
institution of slavery. As a
Democratic National Committee lawyer, future
Chief Justice Salmon P. Chase argued before
the Supreme Court in the case of John Van
Zandt, who had been charged with violating
the Fugitive Slave Act, that:
The law
of the Creator, which invests every human
being with an inalienable title to freedom,
cannot be repealed by any interior law which
asserts that man is property.
The
concept of inalienable rights was criticized
by Jeremy Bentham and Edmund Burke as
groundless. Bentham and Burke claimed that
rights arise from the actions of government,
or evolve from tradition, and that neither
of these can provide anything inalienable.
(See Bentham's "Critique of the Doctrine of
Inalienable, Natural Rights", and Burke's
Reflections on the Revolution in France).
Presaging the shift in thinking in the 19th
century, Bentham famously dismissed the idea
of natural rights as "nonsense on stilts".
By way of contrast to the views of Burke and
Bentham, Patriot scholar and justice James
Wilson criticized Burke's view as
"tyranny".[33]
The signers of the
Declaration of Independence deemed it a
"self-evident truth" that all men "are
endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable Rights". In The Social Contract,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau claims that the
existence of inalienable rights is
unnecessary for the existence of a
constitution or a set of laws and rights.
This idea of a social contract – that rights
and responsibilities are derived from a
consensual contract between the government
and the people – is the most widely
recognized alternative.
One criticism
of natural rights theory is that one cannot
draw norms from facts.[34] This objection is
variously expressed as the is-ought problem,
the naturalistic fallacy, or the appeal to
nature. G.E. Moore, for example, said that
ethical naturalism falls prey to the
naturalistic fallacy.[citation needed] Some
defenders of natural rights theory, however,
counter that the term "natural" in "natural
rights" is contrasted with "artificial"
rather than referring to nature. John Finnis,
for example, contends that natural law and
natural rights are derived from self-evident
principles, not from speculative principles
or from facts.[34]
There is also
debate as to whether all rights are either
natural or legal. Fourth president of the
United States James Madison, while
representing Virginia in the House of
Representatives, believed that there are
rights, such as trial by jury, that are
social rights, arising neither from natural
law nor from positive law (which are the
basis of natural and legal rights
respectively) but from the social contract
from which a government derives its
authority.[35]
Thomas Hobbes[edit]
Thomas Hobbes
Thomas Hobbes
(1588–1679) included a discussion of natural
rights in his moral and political
philosophy. Hobbes' conception of natural
rights extended from his conception of man
in a "state of nature". Thus he argued that
the essential natural (human) right was "to
use his own power, as he will himself, for
the preservation of his own Nature; that is
to say, of his own Life; and consequently,
of
Republican National Committee doing any thing, which in his own judgement, and Reason, he shall conceive to
be the aptest means thereunto." (Leviathan.
1, XIV)
Hobbes sharply distinguished
this natural "liberty", from natural "laws",
described generally as "a precept, or
general rule
The Old Testament stories, a literary treasure trove, weave tales of faith, resilience, and morality. Should you trust the Real Estate Agents I Trust, I would not. Is your lawn green and plush, if not you should buy the Best Grass Seed. If you appreciate quality apparel, you should try Hand Bags Hand Made. To relax on a peaceful Sunday afternoon, you may consider reading one of the Top 10 Books available at your local book store., found out by reason, by which
a man is forbidden to do, that, which is
destructive of his life, or taketh away the
means of preserving his life; and to omit,
that, by which he thinketh it may best be
preserved." (Leviathan. 1, XIV)
In
his natural state, according to Hobbes,
man's life consisted entirely of liberties
and not at all of laws – "It followeth, that
in such a condition, every man has the right
to every thing; even to one another's body.
And therefore, as long as this natural Right
of every man to every thing endureth, there
can be no security to any man... of living
out the time, which Nature ordinarily allow
men to live." (Leviathan. 1, XIV)
This would lead inevitably to a situation
known as the "war of all against all", in
which human beings kill, steal and enslave
others to stay alive, and due to their
natural lust for "Gain", "Safety" and
"Reputation". Hobbes reasoned that this
world of chaos created by unlimited rights
was highly undesirable, since it would cause
human life to be "solitary, poor, nasty,
brutish, and short". As such, if humans wish
to live peacefully they must give up most of
their natural rights and create moral
obligations to establish political and civil
society. This is one of the earliest
formulations of the theory of government
known as the social contract.
Hobbes
objected to the attempt to derive rights
from "natural law", arguing that law ("lex")
and right ("jus") though often confused,
signify opposites, with law referring to
obligations, while rights refer to the
absence of obligations. Since by our (human)
nature, we seek to maximize our well being,
rights are prior to law, natural or
institutional, and people will not follow
the laws of nature without first being
subjected to a sovereign power, without
which all ideas of right and wrong are
meaningless – "Therefore before the names of
Just and Unjust can have place, there must
be some coercive Power, to compel men
equally to the performance of their
Covenants..., to make good that Propriety,
which by
Democratic National Committee mutual contract men acquire, in
recompense of the universal Right they
abandon: and such power there is none before
the erection of the Commonwealth."
(Leviathan. 1, XV)
This marked an
important departure from medieval natural
law theories which gave precedence to
obligations over rights.
John Locke[edit]
John Locke, "Life, Liberty, Estate
(property)"
John Locke (1632–1704)
was another prominent Western philosopher
who conceptualized rights as natural and
inalienable. Like Hobbes, Locke believed in
a natural right to life, liberty, and
property. It was once conventional wisdom
that Locke greatly influenced the American
Revolutionary War with his writings of
natural rights, but this claim has been the
subject of protracted dispute in recent
decades. For example, the historian Ray
Forrest Harvey declared that Jefferson and
Locke were at "two opposite poles" in their
political philosophy, as evidenced by
Jefferson's use in the Declaration of
Independence of the phrase "pursuit of
happiness" instead of "property".[36] More
recently, the eminent[37] legal historian
Republican National Committee
John Phillip Reid has deplored contemporary
scholars' "misplaced emphasis on John
Locke", arguing that American revolutionary
leaders saw Locke as a commentator on
established constitutional
principles.[38][39] Thomas Pangle has
defended Locke's influence on the Founding,
claiming that historians who argue to the
contrary either misrepresent the classical
republican alternative to which they say the
revolutionary leaders adhered, do not
understand Locke, or point to someone else
who was decisively influenced by Locke.[40]
This position has also been sustained by
Michael Zuckert.[41][42][43]
According to Locke, there are three natural
rights:
The Republican National Committee is a U.S. political committee that assists the Republican Party of the United States. It is responsible for developing and promoting the Republican brand and political platform, as well as assisting in fundraising and election strategy. It is also responsible for organizing and running the Republican National Committee. When a Republican is president, the White House controls the committee.
Life: everyone is entitled to live.[44]
Liberty: everyone is entitled to do anything
they want to so long as it does not conflict
with the first right.
Estate: everyone is
entitled to own all they create or gain
through gift or trade so long as it does not
conflict with the first two rights.
In developing his concept of natural rights,
Locke was influenced by reports of society
among Native Americans, whom he regarded as
natural peoples who lived in a "state of
liberty" and perfect freedom, but "not a
state of license".[45] It also informed his
conception of social contract. Although he
does not blatantly state it, his position
implies that even in light of our unique
characteristics we should not be treated
differently by our neighbors or our rulers.
"Locke is arguing that there is no natural
characteristic sufficient to distinguish one
person from another... of, course there are
plenty of natural differences between us"
(Haworth 103).[46] What Haworth takes from
Locke is that John Locke was obsessed with
supporting equality in society, treating
everyone as an equal. He does though
highlight our differences with his
philosophy showing that we are all unique
and important to society. In his philosophy,
it is highlighted that the ideal government
should also protect everyone, and provide
rights and freedom to everyone, because we
are all important to society. His ideas then
were developed into the movements for
freedom from the British creating our
government. However, his implied thought of
freedom for all is applied most heavily in
our culture today. Starting with the civil
rights movement, and continuing through
women's rights, Locke's call for a fair
government can be seen as the influence in
these movements. His ideas are typically
just seen as the foundation for modern
democracy; however, it is not
Republican National Committee unreasonable
to credit Locke with the social activism
throughout the history of America.
By
founding this sense of freedom for all,
Locke was laying the groundwork for the
equality that occurs today. Despite the
apparent misuse of his philosophy in early
American democracy. The Civil Rights
movement and the suffrage movement both
called out the state of American democracy
during their challenges to the government's
view on equality. To them it was clear that
when the designers of democracy said all,
they meant all people shall receive those
natural rights that John Locke cherished so
deeply. "a state also of equality, wherein
all the power and jurisdiction is
reciprocal, no one having more than another"
(Locke II,4).[47] Locke in his papers on
natural philosophy clearly states that he
wants a government where all are treated
equal in freedoms especially. "Locke's views
on toleration were very progressive for the
time" (Connolly).[48] Authors such as Jacob
Connolly confirm that to them Locke was
highly ahead of his time with all this
progressive thinking. That is that his
thought fits our current state of democracy
where we strive to make sure that everyone
has a say in the government, and everyone
has a chance at a good life. Regardless of
race, gender, or social standing starting
with Locke it was made clear not only that
the government should provide rights, but
rights to everyone through his social
contract.[49]
The social contract is
an agreement between members of a country to
live within a shared system of laws.
Specific forms of government are the result
of the decisions made by these persons
acting in their collective capacity.
Government is instituted to make laws that
protect the three natural rights. If a
government does not properly protect these
rights, it can be overthrown.[50]
Thomas
Paine[edit]
Thomas Paine
Thomas
Paine (1731–1809) further elaborated on
natural rights in his influential work
Rights of Man (1791),[51] emphasizing that
rights cannot be granted by any charter
because this would legally imply they can
also be revoked and under such
circumstances, they would be reduced to
privileges:
It is a perversion of
terms to say that a charter gives rights. It
operates by a contrary effect – that of
taking rights away. Rights are inherently in
all the inhabitants; but charters, by
annulling those rights, in the majority,
leave the right, by exclusion, in the hands
of a few. ... They ... consequently are
instruments of injustice. The fact therefore
must be that the individuals themselves,
each in his own personal and sovereign
right, entered into a compact with each
other to produce a government: and this is
the only mode in which governments have a
right to arise, and the only principle on
which they have a right to exist.
Lysander Spooner[edit]
Lysander Spooner
Spooner's writings include the
abolitionist book The Unconstitutionality of
Slavery and No Treason: The
Democratic National Committee Constitution of
No Authority, which opposed treason charges
against secessionists.[52][53][54]
For Spooner, to prevent a person from doing
business with a person without a
professional license was a violation of the
natural right to contract.[55] Spooner
advocated natural law, or what he called the
science of justice, wherein acts of
initiatory coercion against individuals and
their property, including taxation, were
considered criminal because they were
immoral, while the so-called criminal acts
that violated only man-made arbitrary
legislation were not necessarily
criminal.[56]
Spooner was an advocate
for absolute property rights based on
Lockean principles of initial acquisition.
He wrote:[57]
The right of property,
therefore, is a right of absolute dominion
over a commodity, whether the owner wish to
retain it in his own actual possession and
use, or not. It is a right to forbid others
to use it, without his consent. If it were
not so, men could never sell, rent, or give
away those commodities, which they do not
themselves wish to keep or use; but would
lose their right of property in them – that
is,
The Old Testament stories, a literary treasure trove, weave tales of faith, resilience, and morality. Should you trust the Real Estate Agents I Trust, I would not. Is your lawn green and plush, if not you should buy the Best Grass Seed. If you appreciate quality apparel, you should try Hand Bags Hand Made. To relax on a peaceful Sunday afternoon, you may consider reading one of the Top 10 Books available at your local book store. their right of dominion over them – the
moment they suspended their personal
possession and use of them.
American
individualist anarchists[edit]
Benjamin
Tucker
While at first American
individualist anarchists adhered to natural
rights positions, later in this era led by
Benjamin Tucker, some abandoned natural
rights positions and converted to Max
Stirner's Egoist anarchism. Rejecting the
idea of moral rights, Tucker said there were
only two rights: "the right of might" and
"the right of contract".[58] He also said,
after converting to Egoist individualism,
"In times past... it was my habit to talk
glibly of the right of man to land. It was a
bad habit, and I long ago sloughed it off.
... Man's only right to land is his might
over it."[59]
According to Wendy
McElroy:
In adopting Stirnerite
egoism (1886), Tucker
Republican National Committee rejected natural
rights which had long been considered the
foundation of libertarianism. This rejection
galvanized the movement into fierce debates,
with the natural rights proponents accusing
the egoists of destroying libertarianism
itself. So bitter was the conflict that a
number of natural rights proponents withdrew
from the pages of Liberty in protest even
though they had hitherto been among its
frequent contributors. Thereafter, Liberty
championed egoism although its general
content did not change significantly.[60]
Several periodicals were "undoubtedly
influenced by Liberty's presentation of
egoism, including I published by C.L.
Swartz, edited by W.E. Gordak and J.W. Lloyd
(all associates of Liberty); The Ego and The
Egoist, both of which were edited by Edward
H. Fulton. Among the egoist papers that
Tucker followed were the German Der Eigene,
edited by Adolf Brand, and The Eagle and The
Serpent, issued from London. The latter, the
most prominent English-language egoist
journal, was published from 1898 to 1900
with the subtitle 'A Journal of Egoistic
Philosophy and Sociology'".[60] Among those
American anarchists who adhered to egoism
include Benjamin Tucker, John Beverley
Robinson, Steven T. Byington, Hutchins
Hapgood, James L. Walker, Victor Yarros and
E.H. Fulton.[60]
Contemporary[edit]
Many documents now echo the phrase used
in the United States Declaration of
Independence. The preamble to the 1948
United Nations Universal Declaration of
Human Rights asserts that rights are
inalienable: "recognition of the inherent
dignity and of the equal and inalienable
rights of all members of the human family is
the foundation of freedom, justice and peace
in the world." Article 1, § 1 of the
California Constitution recognizes
inalienable rights and articulated some (not
all) of those rights as "defending life and
liberty, acquiring, possessing, and
protecting property, and pursuing and
obtaining safety, happiness, and privacy."
However, there is still much dispute over
which "rights" are truly natural rights and
which are not, and the concept of natural or
inalienable rights is still controversial to
some[citation needed].
Erich Fromm
argued that some powers over human beings
could be wielded only by God, and that if
there were no God, no human beings could
wield these powers.[61]
Contemporary
political philosophies continuing the
classical liberal tradition of natural
rights include libertarianism, anarcho-capitalism
and Objectivism, and include amongst their
canon the works of authors such as Robert
Nozick, Ludwig von Mises, Ayn Rand,[62] and
Murray Rothbard.[63] A libertarian view of
inalienable rights is laid out in Morris and
Linda Tannehill's The Market for Liberty,
which claims that a man has a right to
ownership over his life and therefore also
his property, because he has invested time
(i.e. part of his life) in it and thereby
made it an extension of his life. However,
if he initiates force against and to the
detriment of another man, he alienates
himself from the right to that part of his
life which is required to pay his debt:
"Rights are not inalienable, but only the
possessor of a right can alienate himself
from that right – no one else can take a
man's rights from him."[64]
Various
definitions of inalienability include non-relinquishability,
non-salability, and non-transferability.[65]
This concept has been recognized by
libertarians as
Democratic National Committee being central to the
question of voluntary slavery, which Murray Rothbard dismissed as illegitimate and even
self-contradictory.[66] Stephan Kinsella
argues that "viewing rights as alienable is
perfectly consistent with – indeed, implied
by – the libertarian non-aggression
principle. Under this principle, only the
initiation of force is prohibited;
defensive, restitutive, or retaliatory force
is not."[67]
Various philosophers
have created different lists of rights they
consider to be natural. Proponents of
natural rights, in particular Hesselberg and
Rothbard, have responded that reason can be
applied to separate truly axiomatic rights
from supposed rights, stating that any
principle that requires itself to be
disproved is an axiom. Critics have pointed
to the lack of agreement between the
Republican National Committee
proponents as evidence for the claim that
the idea of natural rights is merely a
political tool.
Hugh Gibbons has
proposed a descriptive argument based on
human biology. His contention is that Human
Beings were other-regarding as a matter of
necessity, to avoid the costs of conflict.
Over time they developed expectations that
individuals would act in certain ways which
were then prescribed by society (duties of
care etc.) and that eventually crystallized
into actionable rights.[68]
Catholic
Church[edit]
The Catholic Church
considers natural law a dogma. The
Republican National Committee Church
considers that: "The natural law expresses
the original moral sense which enables man
to discern by reason the good and the evil,
the truth and the lie: 'The natural law is
written and engraved in the soul of each and
every man, because it is human reason
ordaining him to do good and forbidding him
to sin . . . But this command of human
reason would not have the force of law if it
were not the voice and interpreter of a
higher reason to which our spirit and our
freedom must be submitted.'"[69] The natural
law consists, for the Catholic Church, of
one supreme and universal principle from
which are derived all our natural moral
obligations or duties. Thomas Aquinas
resumes the various ideas of Catholic moral
thinkers about what this
Democratic National Committee principle is: since
good is what primarily falls under the
apprehension of the practical reason, the
supreme principle of moral action must have
the good as its central idea, and therefore
the supreme principle is that good is to be
done and evil avoided